Logic List Mailing Archive

Frege in Leiden

21 October 2011
Leiden, The Netherlands

Frege in Leiden

Friday, October 21, 2011

Room C006, Kamerling Onnes Gebouw, Steenschur 25, Leiden

Programme

10.00  Maria van der Schaar (Leiden)  Judgement and the judgemental force

11.00  Harm Boukema (Nijmegen)  Frege's missing link

14.00  Göran Sundholm (Leiden)  Making sense of truth-values: Frege in 
mysterious circumstances

15.00  Ansten Klev (Leiden)  On Frege's notion of pseudo-axiom

16.30  Kai Wehmeier (Irvine)  Frege's proof of Hume's Principle (joint work 
with Robert May)


Abstracts

Maria van der Schaar (Leiden)  Judgement and judgemental force

Today, most writings on Frege?s notion of judgement focus on the term 
?acknowledgement? (?Anerkennung?) in Frege?s assertion that judgement is 
the acknowledgement of the truth of a proposition. One should not forget, 
though, that judgement, for Frege, is the logically primitive activity 
(logische Urtätigkeit) that is indefinable. Judging is therefore not to be 
understood as a special case of the genus acknowledging, and one should 
not take the term ?acknowledgement? too literal.

The aim of my talk is to elucidate Frege?s notion of judgement by means of 
examples of those judgements that are inferences. Thus hoping to make 
clear how, for Frege, the logical laws, the laws of truth, may constitute 
a norm for our practice of judgement and inference.


Harm Boukema (Nijmegen)  Frege's missing link

In his article Funktion und Begriff, Frege illustrates his distinction 
between functions and objects by means of a very simple and remarkable 
geometrical example: the division of a segment. Even in such a case, where 
at first sight there seems to be involved no dissimilarity at all, its 
parts actually differ in form. For if the dividing point, say C, is not 
counted twice, it can only belong to one of the two parts. The other part 
will be a half open segment. If [A,B] is assumed to be the whole, it may 
be divided in [A,C] and (C,B] or in [A,C) and [C,B]. In other words: the 
two parts only fit if one of them lacks C. No link between them is needed, 
because the missing itself is the link.

In this lecture, it will be argued that, although this piece of analysis 
seems to be impeccable, something of mathematical and logical importance 
has been overlooked, namely that, nevertheless, the point C has to be 
mentioned twice. Awareness of the serious nature of this failure 
constitutes the missing link with a form of analysis different from the 
one applied by Frege and prevailing in analytic philosophy.


Göran Sundholm (Leiden)  Making sense of truth-values: Frege in mysterious 
circumstances

It is hard to conceive of a notion more central to today's philosophy of 
language and logic that that of a truth-value. Frege's explanations, when 
introducing the notion of a truth-value around 1890 are examined and found 
wanting; his formulation in terms of "circumstances" will be rejected and, 
in connection with it, an almost universal mistranslation corrected. It is 
suggested that the origin for the notion of truth-value does not lie 
within the "philosophy of language". On the contrary, the reason for its 
introduction is purely technical. It resides in Frege's (and everyone 
else's) use of the notion of ordered pair in attempts to prove Dedekind's 
theorem on definitions by recursion over the natural numbers.


Ansten Klev (Leiden)  On Frege's notion of pseudo-axiom

In the second series of his Über die Grundlagen der Geometrie (1906) Frege 
interprets Hilbert's axiomatic presentation of geometry (1899) as 
an allgemeiner Lehrsatz, that is, as a conditional whose antecedent is the 
conjunction of the axioms, whose consequent is a conjunction of theorems, 
and in which the primitive terms are replaced by free variables. Frege 
calls the axioms as they occur in such a Lehrsatz `pseudo-axioms'. In the 
secondary literature on Frege and Hilbert it seems to me univocally 
assumed that these axioms are pseudo solely in virtue of their containing 
free variables. This assumption, however, is in conflict with how Frege 
viewed free variables throughout his career, namely as signs that bestow 
generality upon the sentences in which they occur. It is also in conflict 
with Frege's explanation of why he uses the pre-fix `pseudo'. An 
Hilbertean axiom is pseudo, he says, because the free variables that occur 
in it can exercise their function, namely that of bestowing generality, 
only within the larger context of the Lehrsatz. Hence, as separated from 
this whole, a pseudo-axiom is meaningless; Frege therefore also describes 
pseudo-axioms as dependent parts of theLehrsatz.


Kai Wehmeier (Irvine)  Frege's proof of Hume's Principle

In §53 of Grundgesetze, Frege begins to prove what he calls the "basic 
laws of cardinal number". We explore the initial part of his development 
of arithmetic through theorems (32) and (49), which when taken together 
essentially constitute what we call today Hume?s Principle (HP). Frege 
outlined a proof of HP already in Grundlagen §73. The informal exposition 
there has a characteristic asymmetry that is carried over to the formal 
presentation of Grundgesetze: In both, pride of place is given to the 
proof of the "right-to-left direction", F ~ G -> #F = #G. In Grundlagen, 
this direction is discussed in the main body of the text, while the 
provability of the reverse direction is merely mentioned in a footnote. 
In Grundgesetze, the right-to-left direction, i.e. Theorem 32, is accorded 
the status of a Basic Law of Cardinal Number, a status that Theorem 49, 
the left-to-right direction, lacks. Why does Frege differentiate the 
two directions of HP in this way, and why does he never bring 
them together into a biconditional?


The symposium is kindly supported by the Vereniging voor Logica.